Difference between revisions of "Downgrade"

From emcawiki
Jump to: navigation, search
Line 10: Line 10:
 
(i) The term downgrading has been applied to ''toned-down versions of others’ prior claims or descriptions''. In particular, this has often referred to subsequent '''[[Assessment|assessments]]''', where participants ascribe a referent the same properties as others previously have, but to a lower degree (Pomerantz 1984). This might be accomplished lexically by reversing the procedures associated with '''[[Upgrade|upgrading]]''', e.g., selecting an evaluative term that is weaker on some semantic scale (e.g., ''nice'' as a downgrade of ''beautiful''), excluding an intensifying modifier previously used (e.g., ''nice'' as a downgrade of ''really nice'') or including a mitigating modifier (e.g., ''kind of'' or ''pretty'') (Ogden 2006; Pomerantz 1984; Thompson, et al. 2015). Within assessment sequences, downgraded assessments convey weak or pro forma agreement, typically projecting disagreement or other disaligning actions. This is illustrated in the following extract, taken from Ogden (2006):
 
(i) The term downgrading has been applied to ''toned-down versions of others’ prior claims or descriptions''. In particular, this has often referred to subsequent '''[[Assessment|assessments]]''', where participants ascribe a referent the same properties as others previously have, but to a lower degree (Pomerantz 1984). This might be accomplished lexically by reversing the procedures associated with '''[[Upgrade|upgrading]]''', e.g., selecting an evaluative term that is weaker on some semantic scale (e.g., ''nice'' as a downgrade of ''beautiful''), excluding an intensifying modifier previously used (e.g., ''nice'' as a downgrade of ''really nice'') or including a mitigating modifier (e.g., ''kind of'' or ''pretty'') (Ogden 2006; Pomerantz 1984; Thompson, et al. 2015). Within assessment sequences, downgraded assessments convey weak or pro forma agreement, typically projecting disagreement or other disaligning actions. This is illustrated in the following extract, taken from Ogden (2006):
  
  [nrb/01.reluctant lover] (Ogden 2006]
+
  [nrb/01.reluctant lover]
 
   
 
   
 
  01  K:  =she’s- she’s- she’s <u>rea:l</u>ly nice in’t [she   
 
  01  K:  =she’s- she’s- she’s <u>rea:l</u>ly nice in’t [she   
Line 30: Line 30:
 
(iv) Furthermore, in a somewhat different sense of the term, the point of comparison for downgrading may not be prior talk, but some unmarked turn design that ''could'' have been produced in that sequential position. As an example, in responses to ''how are you''-questions, a downgraded response might be for instance ''oh alright'' or ''pretty good'', as compared with a neutral or conventional ''fine''. Such downgraded responses to ''how are you''’s may foreshadow troubles-tellings (Heritage 1998; Jefferson 1980).
 
(iv) Furthermore, in a somewhat different sense of the term, the point of comparison for downgrading may not be prior talk, but some unmarked turn design that ''could'' have been produced in that sequential position. As an example, in responses to ''how are you''-questions, a downgraded response might be for instance ''oh alright'' or ''pretty good'', as compared with a neutral or conventional ''fine''. Such downgraded responses to ''how are you''’s may foreshadow troubles-tellings (Heritage 1998; Jefferson 1980).
  
Like upgrading, the term 'downgrading' may also refer to fine-tuning of '''[[Epistemics|epistemic]]''' and '''[[Deontics|deontic]]''' claims. Epistemically downgrading a turn is done through turn-design that claims comparatively less direct or less certain knowledge of the referent or the state of affairs referred to (Raymond &amp; Heritage 2006). Indirect or mediated knowledge (or access) may be marked as evidential indexing (lexically, e.g., ''I hear'' or ''it seems''), whereas degree of certainty may be marked lexically (e.g., ''I think'') or grammatically (e.g., question tags in English; or a question-final ''or'', see Drake 2015; or through final particles in Mandarin, see Kendrick 2018).
+
(v) Like upgrading, the term 'downgrading' may also refer to fine-tuning of '''[[Epistemics|epistemic]]''' and '''[[Deontics|deontic]]''' claims. Epistemically downgrading a turn is done through turn-design that claims comparatively less direct or less certain knowledge of the referent or the state of affairs referred to (Raymond &amp; Heritage 2006). Indirect or mediated knowledge (or access) may be marked as evidential indexing (lexically, e.g., ''I hear'' or ''it seems''), whereas degree of certainty may be marked lexically (e.g., ''I think'') or grammatically (e.g., question tags in English; or a question-final ''or'', see Drake 2015; or through final particles in Mandarin, see Kendrick 2018).
  
 
In the domain of deontics, downgrading of deontic authority may amount for instance to turn design features (e.g., '''[[Account|accounts]]''', or prefaces like ''I was thinking''…) that make a proposal hearable as inviting acceptance, where it might otherwise be heard as a directive requiring compliance, due to the deontic status associated with the position of power held by the speaker relative to other participants in societal or institutional structures (Stevanovic 2013, 2018). Typically, these epistemic and deontic uses of the term downgrading are understood as relative not to prior talk, but to what would be a neutral or normative turn format in that place in sequence (cf. iv above).
 
In the domain of deontics, downgrading of deontic authority may amount for instance to turn design features (e.g., '''[[Account|accounts]]''', or prefaces like ''I was thinking''…) that make a proposal hearable as inviting acceptance, where it might otherwise be heard as a directive requiring compliance, due to the deontic status associated with the position of power held by the speaker relative to other participants in societal or institutional structures (Stevanovic 2013, 2018). Typically, these epistemic and deontic uses of the term downgrading are understood as relative not to prior talk, but to what would be a neutral or normative turn format in that place in sequence (cf. iv above).

Revision as of 06:35, 27 September 2023

Encyclopedia of Terminology for CA and IL: Downgrade
Author(s): Rasmus Persson (Uppsala University, Sweden) (https://orcid.org/0000-0001-7253-9636)
To cite: Person, Rasmus. (2023). Downgrade. In Alexandra Gubina, Elliott M. Hoey & Chase Wesley Raymond (Eds.), Encyclopedia of Terminology for Conversation Analysis and Interactional Linguistics. International Society for Conversation Analysis (ISCA). DOI: []


A downgrade (or downgrading, downgraded) has been used in slightly different ways throughout the CA and IL literature, but always with a general sense of scaling down or attenuating a turn or action, usually with respect to something prior. The point of comparison may either be others’ prior talk or one’s own talk, or some unmarked default turn design, against which different alternative formulations are measured.

More specific senses can be identified in particular sequential contexts, for instance:

(i) The term downgrading has been applied to toned-down versions of others’ prior claims or descriptions. In particular, this has often referred to subsequent assessments, where participants ascribe a referent the same properties as others previously have, but to a lower degree (Pomerantz 1984). This might be accomplished lexically by reversing the procedures associated with upgrading, e.g., selecting an evaluative term that is weaker on some semantic scale (e.g., nice as a downgrade of beautiful), excluding an intensifying modifier previously used (e.g., nice as a downgrade of really nice) or including a mitigating modifier (e.g., kind of or pretty) (Ogden 2006; Pomerantz 1984; Thompson, et al. 2015). Within assessment sequences, downgraded assessments convey weak or pro forma agreement, typically projecting disagreement or other disaligning actions. This is illustrated in the following extract, taken from Ogden (2006):

[nrb/01.reluctant lover]

01  K:   =she’s- she’s- she’s rea:lly nice in’t [she  
02  J:                                          [she is nice=
03       =.h I do find that she just says stuff just for the sake of
04       £saying stu[(h)uff though£
05  K:              [yeah

A special situation pertains when the first assessment is a compliment: responding with a downgraded assessment may then serve to manage cross-cutting preferences for agreement and avoidance of self-praise (Pomerantz 1978).

(ii) In other sequential contexts, participants may downgrade their own prior talk by producing subsequent versions of it, and in each case the downgrading may be accomplished in a different way. For instance, in so-called concessive repair, extreme case formulations or other overstatements are subsequently downgraded: the speaker of the original claim or description concedes some exception(s) and grants that the claim/description was in part unjustified, before producing a revised version that is weakened, qualified, or restricted (Couper-Kuhlen & Thompson 2005). This often takes the form of downgrading the claim by selecting an item that is lower on some locally relevant semantic or pragmatic scale of ordered expressions, for instance quantifiers ⟨all, most, many, a few⟩. Thus, an overstatement (everyone has a gun) may, after a concession (not everyone), be downgraded to a version with a quantifier lower on the scale (but a lot of people have guns; Couper-Kuhlen & Thompson 2005: 258). Such concessive repair may be produced in response to challenges by co-participants (either on-record or anticipated), or in response to relevantly missing uptake (see also Pfänder 2016).

Relatedly, revised versions of complaints and criticisms, in the face of problems of uptake, can be designed so as to be understood as downgraded with respect to previous versions. In such cases, downgrading may amount to making a more reasonable or less exaggerated claim about the complainable, sometimes formulating a complaint in entirely different terms instead of scaling down the original assertion (Weatherall 2011).

As another example, following non-lexical “moans” by players in board game interactions (Hofstetter 2020), such players may subsequently downgrade their own display of in-game suffering, where the downgrading then amounts to verbal utterances that present the suffering as less severe (e.g., bummer).

(iii) Particularly in interactional linguistics, a phonetic sense of the term downgrading refers to the opposite features of phonetic upgrading, i.e., some or all of the following: reduced pitch span or lower pitch placement in the speaker’s range, reduced loudness, shorter durations of segments, and more open and lax articulatory settings compared with (some specific bit of) prior talk (Couper-Kuhlen 2012; Ogden 2006; Plug 2014).

(iv) Furthermore, in a somewhat different sense of the term, the point of comparison for downgrading may not be prior talk, but some unmarked turn design that could have been produced in that sequential position. As an example, in responses to how are you-questions, a downgraded response might be for instance oh alright or pretty good, as compared with a neutral or conventional fine. Such downgraded responses to how are you’s may foreshadow troubles-tellings (Heritage 1998; Jefferson 1980).

(v) Like upgrading, the term 'downgrading' may also refer to fine-tuning of epistemic and deontic claims. Epistemically downgrading a turn is done through turn-design that claims comparatively less direct or less certain knowledge of the referent or the state of affairs referred to (Raymond & Heritage 2006). Indirect or mediated knowledge (or access) may be marked as evidential indexing (lexically, e.g., I hear or it seems), whereas degree of certainty may be marked lexically (e.g., I think) or grammatically (e.g., question tags in English; or a question-final or, see Drake 2015; or through final particles in Mandarin, see Kendrick 2018).

In the domain of deontics, downgrading of deontic authority may amount for instance to turn design features (e.g., accounts, or prefaces like I was thinking…) that make a proposal hearable as inviting acceptance, where it might otherwise be heard as a directive requiring compliance, due to the deontic status associated with the position of power held by the speaker relative to other participants in societal or institutional structures (Stevanovic 2013, 2018). Typically, these epistemic and deontic uses of the term downgrading are understood as relative not to prior talk, but to what would be a neutral or normative turn format in that place in sequence (cf. iv above).


Additional Related Entries:


Cited References:

Couper-Kuhlen, E. (2012). Exploring affiliation in the reception of conversational complaint stories. In M.-L. Sorjonen & A. Peräkylä (Eds.), Emotion in Interaction (pp. 113–146). Oxford University Press.

Couper-Kuhlen, E., & Thompson, S. A. (2005). A linguistic practice for retracting overstatements: ‘Concessive repair’. In A. Hakulinen & M. Selting (Eds.), Syntax and Lexis in Conversation: Studies on the Use of Linguistic Resources in Talk-in-Interaction (pp. 257–288). Benjamins.

Drake, V. (2015). Indexing uncertainty: The case of turn-final or. Research on Language and Social Interaction, 48(3), 301–318.

Heritage, J. (1998). Oh-prefaced responses to inquiry. Language in Society, 27(3), 291–334.

Hofstetter, E. (2020). Nonlexical “moans”: Response cries in board game interactions. Research on Language and Social Interaction, 53(1), 42–65.

Jefferson, G. (1980). On ‘trouble-premonitory’ response to inquiry. Sociological Inquiry, 50(3–4), 153–185.

Kendrick, K. H. (2018). Adjusting epistemic gradients: The final particle ba in Mandarin Chinese conversation. East Asian Pragmatics, 3(1), 5–26.

Ogden, R. (2006). Phonetics and social action in agreements and disagreements. Journal of Pragmatics, 38(10), 1752–1775.

Pfänder, S. (2016). Fragmented adverbial clauses as resources for negotiating alignment: Concessive repair patterns in French talk-in-interaction. Language Sciences, 58, 95–110.

Plug, L. (2014). On (or not on) the ‘upgrading–downgrading continuum’. In D. Barth-Weingarten & B. Szczepek Reed (Eds.), Prosodie und Phonetik in der Interaktion – Prosody and Phonetics in Interaction (pp. 70–86). Verlag für Gesprächsforschung.

Pomerantz, A. (1978). Compliment responses: Notes on the co-operation of multiple constraints. In J. Schenkein (Ed.), Studies in the Organization of Conversational Interaction (pp. 79–112). Academic Press.

Pomerantz, A. (1984). Agreeing and disagreeing with assessments: Some features of preferred/dispreferred turn shapes. In J. M. Atkinson & J. Heritage (Eds.), Structures of Social Action: Studies in Conversation Analysis (pp. 57–101). Cambridge University Press.

Raymond, G., & Heritage, J. (2006). The epistemics of social relations: Owning grandchildren. Language in Society, 35(5), 677–705.

Stevanovic, M. (2013). Constructing a proposal as a thought: A way to manage problems in the initiation of joint decision-making in Finnish workplace interaction. Pragmatics, 23(3), 519–544.

Stevanovic, M. (2018). Social deontics: A nano-level approach to human power play. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 48(3), 369–389.

Thompson, S. A., Fox, B. A., & Couper-Kuhlen, E. (2015). Grammar in Everyday Talk: Building Responsive Actions. Cambridge University Press.

Weatherall, A. (2011). I don’t know as a prepositioned epistemic hedge. Research on Language and Social Interaction, 44(4), 317–337.


Additional References:

EMCA Wiki Bibliography items tagged with 'downgrade/downgraded/downgrading'