Difference between revisions of "Allusion"

From emcawiki
Jump to: navigation, search
 
(12 intermediate revisions by 2 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
'''Uwe-A. Küttner''' (Leibniz-Institute for the German Language, Mannheim) (https://orcid.org/0000-0002-1688-0896)
+
{{Infobox cite
 +
| Authors = '''Uwe-A. Küttner''' (Leibniz-Institute for the German Language, Mannheim) (https://orcid.org/0000-0002-1688-0896)
 +
| To cite =  Küttner, Uwe-A. (2023). Allusion. In Alexandra Gubina, Elliott M. Hoey & Chase Wesley Raymond (Eds.), ''Encyclopedia of Terminology for Conversation Analysis and Interactional Linguistics''. International Society for Conversation Analysis (ISCA). DOI: [https://doi.org/10.17605/OSF.IO/P9VKN 10.17605/OSF.IO/P9VKN]
 +
}}
  
To cite: Küttner, Uwe-A. (2023). Allusion. In Alexandra Gubina, Elliott M. Hoey & Chase Wesley Raymond (Eds.), ''Encyclopedia of Terminology for Conversation Analysis and Interactional Linguistics''. International Society for Conversation Analysis (ISCA). DOI: [https://doi.org/10.31235/osf.io/8cs5r 10.31235/osf.io/8cs5r]
+
The term '''allusion''' generally refers to something that has been conveyed inexplicitly in interaction. The term figures most prominently in Schegloff’s (1996) analysis of the practice of confirming allusions. Roughly, this practice consists of a speaker using a full repeat to confirm a co-participant’s '''[[Candidate_understanding|candidate understanding]]''' or interpretation of the speaker’s circumstances (current or past), typically as derived or inferred from the preceding interaction (Bolden 2010). In so doing, the confirming speaker not only confirms the correctness or adequacy of that understanding, but also attends to it as having explicated (or exposed) something that was previously conveyed indirectly (i.e. without having been said in so many words or in ''those'' words specifically). This can be seen in following example, adapted from Schegloff (1996: 186), in which Rita at line 05 forwards a conjecture about how Evelyn came to be in the state of being "a bissl verschickert". By confirming this supposition with a full repeat in line 06, Evelyn not only confirms the correctness of that interpretation, she also communicates that her talk in line 01 can be understood to have previously conveyed this indirectly (i.e. ‘alluded to it’).
  
 +
(Schegloff 1996: 186)
 +
 +
01  Eve:    I fee:l a bi:ssl verschickert.
 +
02          (0.2)
 +
03  Rit:    W-wh<u>y</u>’s’<u>a</u>:t,
 +
04          (0.4)
 +
05  Rit: -> uh you’ve had sump’n t’ dr^ink.=
 +
06  Eve: => =I had sump’n t’ dr<u>i</u>:nk.
 +
07  Rit:    Uh huh
  
'''Definition:'''
+
Allusions and allusiveness are generally hard to evidence empirically, and so care must be exercised in invoking these notions analytically. Moreover, in contrast to its vernacular usage, in analytic practice the term should not be understood to carry implications of intentionality or design (Schegloff 1996: 184; see also Drew 2018: 247). In characterizing Evelyn’s repetitional confirmation in line 06 above as confirming an allusion, no claim is being made as to whether she ‘actually’ alluded to ‘having had something to drink’ (or intended to allude to it) with the formulation she selected in line 01. Descriptively, it is therefore more adequate to say that the repetitional confirmation registers that Rita’s turn has proposed a legitimate inference of something that the preceding talk can be understood to have conveyed without it having been articulated (see also Bolden 2010). One environment in which allusiveness appears to play an important role is in the delivery of bad news, which are typically broached cautiously and (at least initially) often only hinted at (Maynard 2003; Schegloff 1988: 443-445).
 
 
The term '''allusion''' generally refers to something that has been conveyed inexplicitly in interaction. The term figures most prominently in Schegloff’s (1996) analysis of the practice of confirming allusions. Roughly, this practice consists of a speaker using a '''full repeat''' to confirm a co-participant’s '''candidate interpretation''' or '''understanding''' of the speaker’s circumstances (current or past), typically as derived or inferred from the preceding interaction (Bolden 2010). In so doing, the confirming speaker not only confirms the correctness or adequacy of that understanding, but also attends to it as having explicated (or exposed) something that was previously conveyed indirectly (i.e. without having been said in so many words or in ''those'' words specifically). This can be seen in following example, adapted from Schegloff (1996: 186), in which Rita at line 05 forwards a conjecture about how Evelyn came to be in the state of being "a bissl verschickert". By confirming this supposition with a full repeat in line 06, Evelyn not only confirms the correctness of that interpretation, she also communicates that her talk in line 01 can be understood to have previously conveyed this indirectly (i.e. ‘alluded to it’).
 
 
 
[Schegloff 1996: 186]
 
01    Eve: I fee:l a bi:ssl verschickert.
 
02        (0.2)
 
03    Rit: W-wh''y''’s’''a'':t,
 
04        (0.4)
 
05 -&gt; Rit: uh you’ve had sump’n t’ dr^ink.=
 
06 =&gt; Eve: =I had sump’n t’ dr''i'':nk.
 
07    Rit: Uh huh
 
 
 
Allusions and allusiveness are generally hard to evidence empirically, and so care must be exercised in invoking these notions analytically. Moreover, in contrast to its vernacular usage, in analytic practice the term should not be understood to carry implications of intentionality or design (Schegloff 1996: 184; see also Drew 2018: 247). In characterizing Evelyn’s repetitional confirmation in line 06 above as confirming an allusion, no claim is being made as to whether she ‘actually’ alluded to ‘having had something to drink’ (or intended to allude to it) with the formulation she selected in line 01. Descriptively, it is therefore more adequate to say that the repetitional confirmation registers that Rita’s turn has proposed a legitimate inference of something that the preceding talk can be understood to have conveyed without it having been articulated (see also Bolden 2010). One environment in which allusiveness appears to play an important role is in the '''delivery of bad news''', which are typically broached cautiously and (at least initially) often only hinted at (Schegloff 1988: 443-445; Maynard 2003).
 
  
  
Line 35: Line 34:
 
Drew, P. (2018). Inferences and indirectness in interaction. ''Open Linguistics'' 4(1), 241-259.
 
Drew, P. (2018). Inferences and indirectness in interaction. ''Open Linguistics'' 4(1), 241-259.
  
Maynard, D. W. (2003). ''Bad news, good news: Conversational order in everyday talk and clinical settings''. University of Chicago Press.
+
Maynard, D. W. (2003). ''Bad News, Good News: Conversational Order in Everyday Talk and Clinical Settings''. University of Chicago Press.
  
 
Schegloff, E. A. (1988). On an actual virtual servo-mechanism for guessing bad news: A single case conjecture. ''Social Problems'' 35 (4), 442-457.
 
Schegloff, E. A. (1988). On an actual virtual servo-mechanism for guessing bad news: A single case conjecture. ''Social Problems'' 35 (4), 442-457.
Line 44: Line 43:
 
'''Additional References:'''  
 
'''Additional References:'''  
  
Pomerantz, A. (2017). Inferring the purpose of a prior query and responding accordingly. In: Raymond, G., Lerner, G. H. &amp; Heritage, J. (eds.). Enabling human conduct: Studies of talk-in-interaction in honor of Emanuel A. Schegloff. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. pp. 61-77.
+
Pomerantz, A. (2017). Inferring the purpose of a prior query and responding accordingly. In Raymond, G., Lerner, G. H. &amp; Heritage, J. (Eds.). ''Enabling Human Conduct: Studies of Talk-in-interaction in Honor of Emanuel A. Schegloff'' (pp. 61-77). John Benjamins.
  
 
Walker, T., Drew, P. &amp; Local, J. (2011). Responding indirectly. ''Journal of Pragmatics'' 43, 2432-2451.
 
Walker, T., Drew, P. &amp; Local, J. (2011). Responding indirectly. ''Journal of Pragmatics'' 43, 2432-2451.
  
  
=== Bibliography items tagged with 'allusion' ===
+
=== EMCA Wiki Bibliography items tagged with 'allusion' ===
 
{{#widget:Iframe
 
{{#widget:Iframe
 
|url=https://emcawiki.net/bibtex/browser.php?keywords=Allusion&bib=emca.bib
 
|url=https://emcawiki.net/bibtex/browser.php?keywords=Allusion&bib=emca.bib
 
|border=0
 
|border=0
 
}}
 
}}

Latest revision as of 20:09, 22 December 2023

Encyclopedia of Terminology for CA and IL: Allusion
Author(s): Uwe-A. Küttner (Leibniz-Institute for the German Language, Mannheim) (https://orcid.org/0000-0002-1688-0896)
To cite: Küttner, Uwe-A. (2023). Allusion. In Alexandra Gubina, Elliott M. Hoey & Chase Wesley Raymond (Eds.), Encyclopedia of Terminology for Conversation Analysis and Interactional Linguistics. International Society for Conversation Analysis (ISCA). DOI: 10.17605/OSF.IO/P9VKN


The term allusion generally refers to something that has been conveyed inexplicitly in interaction. The term figures most prominently in Schegloff’s (1996) analysis of the practice of confirming allusions. Roughly, this practice consists of a speaker using a full repeat to confirm a co-participant’s candidate understanding or interpretation of the speaker’s circumstances (current or past), typically as derived or inferred from the preceding interaction (Bolden 2010). In so doing, the confirming speaker not only confirms the correctness or adequacy of that understanding, but also attends to it as having explicated (or exposed) something that was previously conveyed indirectly (i.e. without having been said in so many words or in those words specifically). This can be seen in following example, adapted from Schegloff (1996: 186), in which Rita at line 05 forwards a conjecture about how Evelyn came to be in the state of being "a bissl verschickert". By confirming this supposition with a full repeat in line 06, Evelyn not only confirms the correctness of that interpretation, she also communicates that her talk in line 01 can be understood to have previously conveyed this indirectly (i.e. ‘alluded to it’).

(Schegloff 1996: 186)

01  Eve:    I fee:l a bi:ssl verschickert.
02          (0.2)
03  Rit:    W-why’s’a:t,
04          (0.4)
05  Rit: -> uh you’ve had sump’n t’ dr^ink.=
06  Eve: => =I had sump’n t’ dri:nk.
07  Rit:    Uh huh

Allusions and allusiveness are generally hard to evidence empirically, and so care must be exercised in invoking these notions analytically. Moreover, in contrast to its vernacular usage, in analytic practice the term should not be understood to carry implications of intentionality or design (Schegloff 1996: 184; see also Drew 2018: 247). In characterizing Evelyn’s repetitional confirmation in line 06 above as confirming an allusion, no claim is being made as to whether she ‘actually’ alluded to ‘having had something to drink’ (or intended to allude to it) with the formulation she selected in line 01. Descriptively, it is therefore more adequate to say that the repetitional confirmation registers that Rita’s turn has proposed a legitimate inference of something that the preceding talk can be understood to have conveyed without it having been articulated (see also Bolden 2010). One environment in which allusiveness appears to play an important role is in the delivery of bad news, which are typically broached cautiously and (at least initially) often only hinted at (Maynard 2003; Schegloff 1988: 443-445).


Additional Related Entries:


Cited References:

Bolden, G. B. (2010). ‘Articulating the unsaid’ via and-prefaced formulations of others’ talk. Discourse Studies 12 (1), 5-32.

Drew, P. (2018). Inferences and indirectness in interaction. Open Linguistics 4(1), 241-259.

Maynard, D. W. (2003). Bad News, Good News: Conversational Order in Everyday Talk and Clinical Settings. University of Chicago Press.

Schegloff, E. A. (1988). On an actual virtual servo-mechanism for guessing bad news: A single case conjecture. Social Problems 35 (4), 442-457.

Schegloff, E. A. (1996). Confirming allusions: Toward an empirical account of action. American Journal of Sociology 102 (1), 161-216.


Additional References:

Pomerantz, A. (2017). Inferring the purpose of a prior query and responding accordingly. In Raymond, G., Lerner, G. H. & Heritage, J. (Eds.). Enabling Human Conduct: Studies of Talk-in-interaction in Honor of Emanuel A. Schegloff (pp. 61-77). John Benjamins.

Walker, T., Drew, P. & Local, J. (2011). Responding indirectly. Journal of Pragmatics 43, 2432-2451.


EMCA Wiki Bibliography items tagged with 'allusion'